The Diaphanous Model of Awareness: Using Illusions as Argumentsby Francois TremblayThe Diaphanous Fallacy is an interesting topic in the objective vs skeptic debate because it is committed by many skeptical arguments. This model of awareness is based on a fundamental misconception between first-person and third-person perspectives, transposing attributes that do not pertain to each other. This misconception is then used as an argument to deny the possibility of “true knowledge”. As I mentioned, the Diaphanous Model of Awareness consists of three steps, taken from different perspectives. The first step is our self-evident, personal, immediate experience of awareness as a diaphanous phenomenon: what we can call the subjective perspective. The second step is our scientific, constructed, non-immediate experience of awareness as a brain-based phenomenon: what we can call the objective perspective. The third step happens when we transpose the appearances of the subjective perspective into requirements for the objective perspective. This is where the fallacy comes in. Because awareness subjectively appears to us as a self-evident and immediate experience, it must be self-evident and immediate in order to be “true” awareness.
This is a naive view of awareness: there is no reason why the way something appears to us must reflect how it really is. This is similar to the naive view of perception I discussed in my article ‘The Infallibility of Sense Perception’. According to this view, the way things appear to us is the way things really are. If we see an oasis in the middle of a desert, it cannot be a mirage – everything is as it appears. Likewise, the diaphanous model transposes appearance (which is, as we know from science, filtered by the brain) as objective reality. The fallacy can be explained more simply in this way. The diaphanous model demands that we find reality without any identity of our own, basically to have a soul, in order to have “true” knowledge. But this is a contradictory demand: as we know from the law of identity, everything that exists has a specific identity. For our awareness to exist, it must likewise have an identity, it must treat and filter information in some way, it cannot be “diaphanous”. The fact that we cannot examine reality without treating the sensory information that tells us about it, does not mean that we do not have “true” knowledge. We gain knowledge precisely by appreciating our limits and propensities for error, and remedying to them by the process of epistemology. To ignore those limits and propensities, is to give a blank check to error. But this does not mean that the task is impossible. By following a process of reason, and going as far as the objective evidence we possess will take us, no more no less, we can achieve a great deal of knowledge, as the progress of science in the past century has taught us. As I mentioned, the diaphanous fallacy is applied to a number of epistemic and ethical concepts, such as sense perception, free will, morality, the undefined potentiality objection, and the Descartian subjectivist arguments. I have already defended sense perception against faith-based and skeptical arguments in the article linked above. I will briefly address it again, as well as two other concepts, to illustrate how the diaphanous fallacy operates. The main skeptic objection to the infallibility of sense perception consists of pointing out that naive realism – that is, the view that the immediate appearance of exterior objects is automatically valid – is incorrect. Our immediate experience of objects, for instance mirages, can be revealed to be false. We find that sense perception depends on context as well. Therefore, they argue that sense perception is not diaphanous, and therefore cannot be trusted in some way. Sensory perception must be mediated by rational thinking about the context and our senses in order to be valid. But this does not mean that it is invalid. In fact, as I explained in the article, sense perception is logically infallible. Free will is often argued against on the basis that it exists within a biological context. To be a “true” free will (and not an “illusion”), it should exist as an uncaused, identity-less cloud floating around the brain, a soul so to speak. Since it is a part of the brain processes, it is therefore invalid in the diaphanous model. The undefined potentiality objection is my name for the proposition that a god could exist regardless of whether we can actually know about it or not, and that this is a good reason to believe. This is usually the last resort of the skeptic’s case against strong-atheism. I already answered to it in the FAQ for “Why can’t you accept there simply are things we do not know about?”. But the point is that the strong-atheist is condemned for being an independent observer with his own limits. Because there may be things outside our understanding, does not provide evidence for such things, especially since we cannot even define them. Thus the skeptic here imposes on us an illogical demand (you must know everything) and when we cannot fulfill this illogical demand, he uses this as an argument against knowledge (which does not include such illogical demands). Ultimately, post-modernism is an extreme form of the diaphanous fallacy, because it demands that “true knowledge” be uninfluenced by all cultural pressure. I say it is an extreme form because it does not demand that the individual be identity-less, but rather that the entire social structure be identity-less. As such, it puts demands on the epistemic process that are qualitatively even more impossible to fulfill. Certainly there are other ways to argue skepticism than the diaphanous model of awareness, but it is a large part of most skeptical positions. Therefore it is very important to understand its reach (to be able to identify it) as well as its refutation. Illustrating the fact that appearance only gives us part of the picture, Leda Cosmides and John Tooley, in “Evolutionary Psychology Primer”, state:
Last updated: 01/01/05 |